Jul 30, 2009

Pakisagot lang po ng maayos!

WHAT DOES YOUR CHURCH WEAR REVEALS ABOUT YOU?

Gaano ka katagal mag-isip ng isusuot sa pagsisimba?
a. Pagkabangon, kung anong soot ko, yun na yun.
b. That morning din lang ako nagdedesisyon.
c. Di na ako nag-iisip kasi uniform ng
collector/choir/layminister/usher/lector ang isosoot ko.
d. Aba, gabi ko pa pinag-isipan yan!
e. Mga one hour, at least.

Anong sa tingin mo ang major criterion sa pagpili ng damit na isusuot sa pagsisimba?
a. Comfort. Antagal kaya ng homily ni Father,
at least, comfortable ako kapag nakatulog sa Mass.
b. Style. Linggo kaya!!! Di ko kayang mag-malling
afterwards kung nakabestida/longsleeves noh?
c. Propriety. According to the Dress Code na
pinalabas ng Diocese, Long Pants and Polo for men,
Manang Skirts for women. Mahirap bang intindihin yun?
d. Stage Presence. I can’t just be there and be lost in the crowd.
e. Audience Impact. Andami kayang taong makakakita sa akin
so why the promdi look diba?

Saan ka madalas umupo sa loob ng simbahan?
a. Sa likuran. Or more precisely, sa tabi ng exit.
b. Sa tabi ng electric fan. Sayang ang porma ko kung
lagkitan naman sa pawis ang leeg ko diba?
c. Sa upuan kung saan may nakalagay na “reserved seats”
kung saan parepareho kami ng soot.
d. As close to the altar as possible.
Para alam ni Father, present ako.
e. Sa gitna ng simbahan, sa tabi ng aisle.
Kapag super-init sa loob ng simbahan
at nagsisimula ka nang magpawis, anong una mong gagawin?
a. Lalabas ng simbahan.
b. Maghahanap ng electric fan.
c. Maglalabas ng abaniko na gawa
sa sandalwood at tatanggalin ang belo.
d. Maglalabas ng Wet Wipes tapos magpapapaypay
sa maid gamit ang isang giant anahaw fan.
e. Maghuhubad.

Ang ultimate Sunday wear para sayo ay:
a. Tee-shirt, slimfit jeans, havaianas o at syempre, i-pod.
b. Cargo pants, merrel sandals at polo shirt sa lalake;
short-sleeved blouse, Crocs at roll-up drawstring pants
naman para sa babae.
c. Damit na pang-first communion o pang-ninong/ninang sa kasal.
d. Kahit na anong disenteng damit basta
match sa jewelries na isusuot ko that day.
e. May isang giant cross sa gitna ng dibdib
tapos nakabelo ng chiffon hanggang talampakan.
Tapos yun lang. As in yun lang.

How much are you willing to spend para sa sa isusuot mo sa Linggo?
a. Not much. Kung ano suot ko sa Linggo,
yun din soot ko sa buong linggo.
b. Depende sa sale na pupuntahan ko mamaya after the Mass.
c. Depende sa sinabi ni Father sa homily nya last Lent.
d. Not much. Mga 50K or so.
e. Tama lang, basta ba maha-highlight ang cleavage/pectorals/abs/pusod ko.

If you would dare to make a fashion comment kay Father, ano ito?
a. Pads,cool sandals natin ah.
b. Father, sa Market! Market! mo rin ba nabili ang shirt mo?
(pre-recorded reply naman ni Father: Naku, regalo lang ‘to!)
c. Padeeehr, bagay na bagay sayo, Padeeehr. (repeat to fade…)
d. Fuhther, what’s your shirt size ba?
I think I just saw a shirt in Milan just for you.
e. Haaayy…Father, masyado ka namang balot na balot!
You shouldn’t hide your assets behind all that cloth.

Kung bibigyan kang pagkakataong damitan ang isang Santo,
ano ang idadamit mo sa kanya?
a. Bakit pa natin papakialaman soot nila.
As if it matters, diba?
b. Maghahanap ako sa Tutuban ng pwedeng pandamit nya.
c. Yarda-yardang telang puti
d. Gold-threaded emsemble, korona at ma-diamanteng “halo”
e. Fig leaf sa private parts atsaka isang apple

How to compute your score: Bilangin mo kung aling letra ang pinakamadalas mong pinipili. Yun ang type of parishioner ka.

Madalas letter A. The Leisurely Slacker. Ang mga taong tumutugma dito ay madalas introverted at may pagka-antisocial. Malapit sila sa Diyos pero sa tao, parang ewan lang. Meron silang cynical na pagtingin sa buhay, pa-artist kuno na attitude at medyo dark na humor, gayun pa man, sila ay larawan din ng tunay na humility. Sila rin ang may pinaka-honest at sincere na opinyon tungkol sa simbahan. Madalas, ang prayer nila ay for inspiration and guidance.

Madalas letter B. The Mallville Citizen. Ang araw ng Linggo at Sabado sa kanila ay sagrado, sagrado for malling purposes. Nagsisimba sila para mahintay ang pagbubukas ng SM. Gayunpaman, ang mga Mallville citizens ang mga pinaka-family oriented, pinakasociable sa lahat. Sila rin ang tunay na nakakaappreciate sa homily ni Father, lalo na kung may pop culture references. Madalas ang prayer nila ay tungkol sa trabaho o kaya ay sa family.

Madalas letter C. The Church Manang/Manong. Unipormado, naka-Avon na pamango, Natasha na footwear at ngiting praktisado, sila ay mga die-hard Sharonians. Madalas, daig pa nila ang parish priest sa pagkaistrikto sa regulations sa simbahan. Madalas ay saulado nilang lahat ang mga kanta sa Mass, pati novena ng Perpetual Help. Malabatas para sa kanila ang mga utos ni Father. Nababalitang mga ipokrita’t tsismosa, pero sa totoo ay kakakikitaan din sila ng pusong tunay na nagnanais maglingkod at dumamay sa iba. Madalas ang dasal nila ay tungkol sa health o sa mga kaanak nila.

Madalas letter D. The Benefactor. Donyahan sa kakinangan. Ang lalaki nama’y mga mukhang pensyonado. Mataas ang pinag-aralan kaya nahuhuli nila ang mga theological palusot ni Padre. Sila ang dahilan kung bakit may budget ang simbahan. Minsan, sila rin ang problema ng parokya dahil sa mga kapritso nila. Madalas pagkamalang isnabero’t matapobre, pero ang totoo’y sabik silang magkaroon ng kaibigan. Madalas ang dasal nila ay tungol sa kaaway o problema sa negosyo o sa mana.

Madalas letter E. The Viva Films Talent. Ang mga babae’y suki ng Southbeach at Xenical. Ang mga lalaki’y tambay sa gym. Mga di mo napapansin noong highschool pero nung nag-bloom eh nasobrahan naman yata. Model-modelan pero ang totoo’y mababa ang self-esteem, mahina ang self-image. Madalas, misunderstood kaya may pagkarebelde at may pagkaloner, pero sila ay mga loyal na kaibigan at mga passionate na syota. Dama nila na kahit simangot ang lahat, eh ”tanggap sila ni Lord.” Madalas ang dasal nila ay tungkol sa true love at everlasting relationship.

O? Ano nang result ng quiz mo? Ishare mo naman!ΓΌ

Jul 23, 2009

40 RULES FOR LIVING

1. Give people more than they expect and do it cheerfully.
2. Memorize your favourite poem.
3. Don't believe all you hear, spend all you have or sleep all you want.
4. When you say, "I love you," mean it.
5. When you say, "I'm sorry," look the person in the eye.
6. Never laugh at anyone's dreams.
7. Love deeply and passionately. You might get hurt but it's the only way to live life completely.
8. Don't judge people by their relatives.
9. Talk slow but think quick.
10. When someone asks you a question you don't want to answer, smile and ask, "Why do you want to know?"
11. Remember that great love and great achievements involve great risk.
12. Call your mom.
13. Say "Bless you" when you hear someone sneeze.
14. When you lose, don't lose the lesson.
15. Remember the three R's: Respect for self; Respect for others; Responsibility for all your actions.
16. Don't let a little dispute injure a great friendship.
17. When you realize you've made a mistake, take immediate steps to correct it.
18. Smile when picking up the phone. The caller will hear it in your voice.
19. Marry someone you love to talk to. As you get older, conversational skills will be as important as any other.
20. Spend some time alone.
21. Open your arms to change, but don't let go of your values.
22. Remember that silence is sometimes the best answer.
23. Read more books and watch less TV.
24. Live a good, honourable life. Then when you get older and think back, you'll get to enjoy it a second time.
25. Trust in God but lock your car.
26. A loving atmosphere in your home is so important. Do all you can to create a tranquil harmonious home.
27. In disagreements with loved ones, deal with the current situation. Don't bring up the past.
28. Read between the lines.
29. Share your knowledge. It's a way to achieve immortality.
30. Be gentle with the earth.
31. Pray -- there's immeasurable power in it.
32. Never interrupt when you are being flattered.
33. Mind your own business.
34. Don't trust a lover who doesn't close his/her eyes when you kiss them.
35. Once a year, go someplace you've never been before.
36. If you make a lot of money, put it to use helping others while you are living. That is wealth's greatest satisfaction.
37. Learn the rules then break some.
38. Remember that the best relationship is one where your love for each other is greater than your need for each other.
39. Judge your success by what you had to give up in order to get it.
40. Remember that your character is your destiny.


Excerpt from " The LIttle Prince" ( The Essence of Love"
“You are beautiful, but you are empty,” he went on. “One could not die for you. To be sure, an ordinary passer-by would think that my rose looked like you – the rose that belongs to me. But in herself alone she is more important than all the hundreds of you other roses: because it is she that I have watered; because it is she that I have sheltered behind the screen; because it is for her that I have killed the caterpillars (except the two or three that we saved to become butterflies); because it is she that I have listened to, when she grumbled, or boasted, or even sometimes when we said nothing. Because she is my rose” (The Little Prince in passing by a garden of roses.)

“My life is very monotonous,” he said. “I hunt chickens, men hunt me. All the chickens are just alike and all men are all alike. And, in consequence; I am a little bored. But if you tame me, it will be as if the sun came to shine on my life. I shall know the sound of a step that will be different from all the others. Other steps send me hurrying back underneath the ground. Yours will call me, like music, out of my burrow. And then look: you see the green grain-fields down yonder? I do not eat bread. Wheat is of no use to me. The wheat fields have nothing to say to me. And that is sad. But you have hair that is the color of gold. Think how wonderful that will be when you have tamed me! The grain, which is also golden, will bring me back the thought of you. And I shall love to listen to the wind in the wheat…” The fox said to the Little Prince.

Jul 21, 2009

Time Machine




Photos for the future





These are my co-journeying people in this lonely universe!

Jul 19, 2009

I have created this to remind me of being and nothingness of this existence!

"I think therefore I am"

Opinion on Faith

GABRIEL MARCEL


Gabriel Marcel (1889–1976) is a French philosopher whose name is linked with “theistic existentialism” in contrast to the atheistic existentialism of J.P. Sartre who was the object of his criticism regarding his views on man, freedom, intersubjectivity, and on God. He preferred however to be considered as a “neo-Socratic” or as a Socratic thinker of the contemporary times. This could be due to his advocacy of a philosophy of dialogue although his central stress on the relation of the I to the thou and to the absolute Thou has an unquestionably existential character. He dealt with such existential themes like the mystery of being, participation, communion, incarnation, man as being in the world, hope, fidelity, among others. These themes were explored insightfully through the employment of his own phenomenological method which he developed in terms of the distinction between primary reflection and secondary reflection. Some of his well-read works are Metaphysical Journal, The Mystery of Being (in 2 volumes), Being and Having, Homo Viator, and Creative Fidelity.
This essay is a reflection on the meaning of faith. Characteristic of Marcel’s phenomenological method, he humbly, honestly, and courageously calls our attention to the spiritual condition of his own personal life: his belief in God seemed to him to have degenerated into an opinion. In other words, his faith is just an idea in his mind because it is devoid of active commitment to God. His reflection on his own spiritual condition has given rise to a fundamental insight which applies to all Christian believers namely, the most harmful symbiosis of belief and unbelief in the same soul. There is a self-alienating dualism or gap which affects many Christian believers insofar as they betray their fundamental duty to be living witnesses of their faith. Every Christian believer must be aware of the possible unbelief which co-exists with his belief that he claims to possess. Hence, reflective self-criticism might disclose that one is both a believer and a non-believer.
Marcel painstakingly showed that faith or belief

is not an opinion. Experience will show that it is inappropriate to say that I have an opinion of a friend, or someone I love, or anyone who is intimately close to me. Reflection will reveal that opinion denotes distance or gap between the self and that of which or of whom I only have an opinion. Opinion is directed then to someone who is not considered as a thou or as a presence but as an object or someone external to me, or someone with whom I am not in communion or with whom I have no participation in being. In this sense, if my faith is degraded to an opinion then God is external to me, He is not really part of my life.
Furthermore, belief is not to be confused also with conviction. It sounds strange that Marcel could not link conviction with belief if one notes that conviction denotes firm adherence to something. In this sense, he who believes is convinced about his belief and is said to cling steadfastly to it. Yet closer examination would also show that conviction also indicates an attitude of “inner closure.” Conviction might turn out to be stubbornness rather than steadfastness since it is devoid of openness of the self. He who is convinced might demonstrate inner harmony which is essential to belief yet he actually bars or encloses himself from participation or communion with others, for his conviction is directed against the other.
Authentic belief could be illustrated by the experience of “giving a credit.” When one gives credit, one actually entrusts a certain amount of money or something to another and the other is deemed worthy of trust. This act of extending credit to another is considered by Marcel as “the most essential and constitutive aspect of belief.” Now, when one believes it is not something but oneself that one gives as credit to another. But strictly speaking, one can only entrust oneself to a “thou,” to a person. For only a person or a “thou” could be invoked, called upon. In this sense, when one believes in God one gives his whole self to God. Hence, to believe in God is to extend one’s whole being as a credit to an absolute Thou. [TGR]



-----------------------------------------------------------------
Those who are acquainted with my work know that the paramount task of philosophy as I conceive it lies in the analysis of certain spiritual situations; these situations must first be circumscribed as carefully as possible and reflection must be induced to revive them for our inner inspection. I wish to adopt this same procedure in approaching the problem which is raised by the coexistence in our society of believers and non-believers.
It is not difficult to see why this problem has remained and will continue to remain in the forefront of my interests. I came to the catholic faith at a late date; my deepest sentiments still ally me with the non-believer; I can understand his difficulties better than others. Hence a personal and somewhat incongruous situation which is fraught with difficulties, but which at least serves to stimulate reflection.
I shall begin with an observation that I owe perhaps to my friend Father Fessards - although I am not altogether sure of this -, one which he has in any case admirably developed in one of his recent works. We shall understand nothing of the relation between the believer and the non-believer and there is danger of giving the most harmfully pharisaic interpretation of it if we fail to perceive something else which is even more mysterious, namely the symbiosis of belief and disbelief in the same soul. If the believer has any duty at all, it is to become aware of all that is within him of the non-believer.
This observation occurred to my mind in an anguished form during the past few month when the pressure of external events had become almost intolerable; I sensed the approach of a disaster in which everything we loved would founder; I said to myself: there is no reason why our worst presentiments should not be realized. Then I took to asking myself: what is becoming of my faith? I did not possess it any longer; to me it seemed devitalized to the point of degenerating into a certain opinion that I recognized as part of my mental furniture, nothing more. I debated with myself: I still cannot blind myself to the facts, I said; there is a kind of facile optimism which I cannot compel myself to adopt; God’s purposes are inscrutable, there is no guarantee that everything I love will not be destroyed. At that period I had some conversations with a catholic friend of mine who had an extremely lucid mind which did not overlook any of the dangers of the present time. His calm at first irritated me; I was inclined to take his composure for indifference; then I suddenly thought: this is a real faith because it brings peace. Peace and faith are inseparable. I shall revert to this relationship later; it seems to me to be of certain importance. I also realized at the same moment that if I was able to recognize his faith for what it was, it was because such faith inhabited me as well; this reflection was a course of encouragement. But the memory of this inner crisis has not left me - in particular, the awareness of the unbridgeable gulf between opinion and faith.
As a matter of fact, I should like to draw the attention of the reader to something which requires considerable development in its own right: it seems clear to me that certain developments in contemporary thought exhibit a tendency to confuse belief with opinion. To someone who does not share my belief, it in fact tends to appear as an opinion; through a commonly known optical illusion, I myself tend to consider it from the point of view of the other person, hence to treat it in turn as an opinion. Thus a strange, disturbing dualism is established within me; to the extent that I in fact live my belief, it is in no way an opinion; to the extent that I describe it to myself, I espouse the point of view of the person who represents it to his mind but does not live it; it then becomes external to me - and, to that degree, I cease to understand myself.
The fact is that if we wish to understand this clearly, we must pay particular attention to the question of what is - and above all what is not - an opinion.
Needless to say, a large part of the following reflections are directly related to the analyses of Plato which are still unrivalled; I note this here to avoid reverting to it again in what follows. My own orientation, however, will be somewhat different; for I am particularly concerned with describing the relation of opinion to belief and faith, not to science; confusion is most to be feared in this connection.
Let us put aside those opinions which are conjectures bearing on some undetermined fact; these will teach us nothing; it may be immediately noted, however, that the proposition with which we shall begin our analysis is perfectly applicable to these “conjectures.” This proposition is as follows.
In general, we only have an opinion of what we do not know; but this lack of knowledge is not discerned, is not avowed. Here, the best example we can take is an opinion of a person. It should be noted at once that we do not have an opinion, strictly speaking, of those beings with whom we are intimately acquainted; this observation is also applicable to artistic works, etc. If someone asks me my opinion about Mozart or Wagner, I do not know what to reply; it is as though my experience were too dense, my cohabitation with Mozart of Wagner too close. I think it can be confirmed in every instance that an opinion can only be established from a certain distance, that it is essentially far-sighted. It remains to be seen whether this far-sightedness is not myopic in certain respects. These metaphors, of course, are always faulty. Nevertheless it is always the case that to the extent that an experience is enriched, perfected, it tends to eliminate those elements of opinion at first hidden within it which were merely stop-gaps.
Let us turn now to the structure of opinion; this in fact is essentially fluctuating; for basically, opinion always glides - in essence - between two limits, one of which is an impression, the other an affirmation; when it is nothing more than an impression, however, it is not really an opinion. In a case of this kind everybody will say when asked: “I only have an impression of him, not an opinion.” (To be sure an uncritical mind is sometimes unable to make this distinction). To my mind, opinion, properly speaking, invariably involves a certain implicit reference to which I cannot find a name in French, a reference to a part of the sentence that is understood: I maintain that . . . . However, it can, and in fact generally does, happen, that the latter remains implicit. Opinions are expressed in propositions which refer to a reality whose roots remain buried; it is just these roots that reflection must expose. It must explain the expression, “I maintain that . . . .” The best way to exasperate a discussant is to supply such an explanation as is implied in the simple remark: “You are the one who said so.” In general, when someone spontaneously affirms of his own opinion: “That is my opinion, I give it to you for what it is worth,” this is a proof of the fact that he does not have too much confidence in it. Language here is wonderfully expressive: “hold,” “maintain.” The manner in which one adheres to something and the manner in which one upholds something are interdependent. To maintain an opinion is to maintain it before someone else, even if this someone be oneself; an opinion which is not maintained is not capable of being so, on the other hand, is not really an opinion. Personally, I am convinced that opinion is impossible without a reference to another. There is an imperceptible transition from “maintain” to “claim,” and I am not using “claim” in its pejorative sense, although here too there is or can be a continuous transition in meaning.
Thus we arrive at another proposition which this time is a definition: in general, an opinion is an appearing to be which tends to change into a claim; and it should at once be added that this occurs because of an absence of reflection; to put it differently, the initial appearing is not understood as such - and it is because of this that it can be mobilized into an opinion. Examples of this are plentiful: I might take as a favorite example the sort of opinion which refers to nationalities of which most of us have only the barest outlines of an experience. “The English are hypocrites, the Russians unreliable.” The implied reference is immediately understood: “I maintain to you that the English are hypocrites, etc.” If we take the trouble to ask ourselves what its, so to speak, goldbacking may be when we have uttered an opinion of this kind, what its cash values is, we would be horrified. Suppose that I have made two or three statements each of which, taken alone, has clearly not been confirmed; let us assume moreover, that no inferences have been drawn from any of them; everything takes place basically on the affective level, the level of impressions; and it is at this moment that the “change” has taken place, that I have converted the impression into an opinion. I have given my opinion, and it is strengthened by being exercised. We have to consider what sort of life it will lead in the future, however. It will tend to nourish itself on everything that is capable of making it stronger. The extent to which we can talk here of a mental biology and of a biology of opinion in particular, is never adequately appreciated. Opinion tends to behave like an autonomous organism which admits into itself whatever is able to strengthen it and which avoids whatever threatens to weaken it.
Up to now we have merely scratched the surface, however; and the reason for this is that we have proceeded in a completely abstract way, as though the subject was isolated, as though it had only its own experience to deal with. Unfortunately, this is not so. Each of us is immersed - and opinion can be understood only if we take account of such immersion. If reflection concentrates on the implicit reference, it will observe how it changes its form. The fact is that in the great majority of cases, it is not I who “maintains that . . . .” If someone presses me when I have just uttered an opinion, I will usually resort to flight, sheltering myself behind “it is said that” or “everyone says.” “Everyone knows that the English are a nation of hypocrites.” Here again we must pause, for a very important feature comes to light. I am afraid that opinion usually has a false basis. I treat something which is not mine as though it were mine, something that I have somehow inhaled without realizing it. We are dealing with a reality which is of an even greater complexity than this, however. The more an opinion is offered as an evaluation, the more we find inextricably mixed in with it both the factor I have just described and another of a different sort that we should now try to grasp.
In these critical years when people are so badly divided in their convictions, it is impossible to avoid being not only preoccupied with, but really haunted by the hybrid mystery concealed behind the word “opinion.” I was recently prompted to say a few words to an audience composed entirely of communists or at least persons inspired by communism. I found it possible to refrain from uttering any words which would offend the audience. But while I also felt a certain basic sympathy for my audience, I at the same time recognized how completely impossible it was to reach them on the level of opinion. Now it is precisely here that we find this complex of factors which are in fact indissociable, but which we must nevertheless analyze with the greatest care. I accept it as a fact that if we try to understand what an adherent of the popular front (evidently assumed to be sincere) thinks, we will find for the most part an acute awareness of certain injustices together with the fundamental evaluations presupposed by this awareness. This does not have the character of an opinion; the injustices are perceived, are flagrant, even if the individual who denounces them has not personally been a victim of them, and particularly so in his case, perhaps. Every assertion of the form: such-and-such cannot be condoned to my mind transcends the plane of opinion. On the other hand, however, as soon as a judgment is uttered on “those really responsible” for this state of affairs, all the observations I have made above, hold; with what authority do I assert that such-and-such a person or even such-and-such a corporation is responsible? What I am doing here is mirroring something else. This involves a transition from “I maintain that” to “Everyone knows” - meaning here “my newspaper said” - without my being able to discern the roots of the statement. Generally, we can say that for the man in the street, “my paper” is something for the idealist; in fact, it is not an exaggeration to say that from a certain point of view “my consciousness” is “my paper.” Yet this is a somewhat unwarranted simplification, because in the first place, I have chosen my paper. A great deal can be said about the meaning and implications of this choice, but it is particularly necessary that “my paper” conforms to a certain mute exigence within me which finds its satisfaction in the paper and which ratifies a posteriori the latter’s statements; and this mute exigence is the basic and irreducible element in my way of evaluating. Here again, however, we have to guard against excessive simplification. We do not have to do with a single exigence, but with a bundle, a skein of exigences. Only a rigorous examination of consciousness can enlighten us in this respect; we must indeed begin with ourselves if we are to discern the role played in our opinion by our own personal interest or by some emotional bias for or against someone. Here again, we shall discover a spectrum of meanings. At the one extreme, opinion is only the expression of a desire or aversion, or of a complex of factors in which desire and aversion are indissolubly mixed; at the opposite extreme, opinion implies inversely, a kind of ideal claim having value in itself, which disregards the interests of the empirical subject who expresses it. The significant point about this, however, is that hypocrisy too often enters in, and allows me to express in terms of an ideal and impersonal claim what in fact is only an appetite - but one which does not dare reveal itself in all its nudity. We have to recognize, nevertheless, that opinion is located just between the two, in this penumbra receptive to mirages and phantoms. Indeed how can we speak of opinion when appetite reveals itself without disguise? Where an intrinsic value is defended, on the other hand, we are in the realm of what I shall call the hyperdoxical.
It follows from the above that if we wish to consider the value of an opinion, a political opinion, for example, a series of preliminary distinctions are required.
First of all we may ask about the meaning or import of the experience underlying an opinion although we cannot establish any equivalence or measure between the two.
On the other hand, and on a wholly different level, we must assign to any opinion whatever, a certain existential significance, insofar as an opinion expresses, whether adequately or not, a set of needs which we cannot abstract.
Finally, the ideal and depersonalized claim which can be concealed in an opinion is a factor which must be treated separately. What must be clearly granted, however, is that the coexistence of such distinct and irreducible factors at the core of opinion compels us to proclaim its essential lack of reality. The mode of relation established by consciousness between these diverse elements will in fact always remain unverifiable.
We must now closely examine the “religious opinions” of the free thinker in the light of the foregoing observations. We shall have hardly any difficulty in rediscovering here the incongruous elements I just now attempted to catalogue. The simplest approach is to consider the case of the atheist who candidly affirms his atheism. The characteristic feature of opinion as such is nowhere more in evidence than here: “I maintain that” God does not exist. Atheism, on the other hand, is something that is affirmed essentially before another, or before oneself insofar as one is another. It is not and cannot be lived as faith. It is essentially a riposte or what amounts to the same thing, an objection. That this I now conceals a one, that it inevitably refers to a “general opinion” conveyed by conversation, the press, books, is so obvious that I believe it unnecessary to pursue the subject any further. What is here of greater moment is to discern the respective contributions made by experience, the existential affirmation, and the ideal claim. To make such a discrimination, moreover, is much more difficult; and nuances of meaning which I cannot introduce here have to be presented.
First of all, the empirical contribution; the “I maintain that” of the atheist implies a “my experience shows me that.” Here an important observation should be made. It seems to me that the atheist claims to conjoin two kinds of observations: one is negative, the other positive (or one he believes to be so - wrongly in all likelihood).
On the one hand he asserts that he has had no experience of God. “If God existed, I would have experienced him.” This is more or less what a person who occupied an important position in the state system of education once affirmed to me.
There is, however, a complement to the above: “On the other hand, I have experienced certain facts which would not have occurred if God existed.” There is absolutely no doubt that the stumbling block of evil in all its guises is one of the bases of atheism. However, we have to analyze this judgment of inconsistency. In fact, if we examine it closely, we will find a paradox. When in talking about a certain person, I say: “if she had been there, such a thing would not have happened,” I base my remark on an exact knowledge or on a knowledge I claim is exact, of the person in question; for example, she would have prevented the child from playing with the matches. This means: she is prudent, careful, good: hence she would not have allowed the child to play with the matches. However, this assumes not only that the person exists, but also that we know his manner of existing. But we can see at once that we are dealing with something different in the case of God. The atheist bases his view on a certain idea of God (not on an experience, clearly). If God existed, he would have such-and-such properties; possessing these properties, he would not allow that . . . . etc. . . . The judgment of inconsistency is based on a judgment involving an implication. Possibly the term “implication” is not strong enough. What is really meant is that to think of God is not to think of anything at all, to limit oneself to the mere utterance of the word “God,” if our affirmation does not involve the existence of a being who is sovereignly good and sovereignly powerful. Now this is justified. But in all likelihood the transition to the conclusion is not justified. Let us consider the example I took from the finite or created order. If Jane had been there she would not have allowed the child to play with the matches. The ground for my statement is either certain analogous cases in which Jane has in fact demonstrated her prudence or, if such cases have not occurred, the consciousness of what I would have done in her place. Is this applicable to the case where we claim to reason about the behavior of God? Clearly not. If I base myself on the consideration of what in fact has been the action of God in such or such a particular circumstance, I put myself in a position where it is impossible to arrive at an atheistic conclusion. Is the second alternative more acceptable? Can I put myself in God’s place in order to affirm that in such-and-such a case I would have acted in such a way, would or would not have allowed such an event to take place, etc.? Something odd takes place here. Whenever we are dealing with an influential person who is responsible for taking the initiative in a difficult situation, we readily recognize that we cannot put ourselves “in his place,” that we do not know ourselves what we would do if we were “in his place.” The politician, however, always seems to be at grips with a situation he has not created, but which he should nevertheless try to control. On the other hand, it can be conceded that God, being thought of as a creator, does not confront an infinitely complex series of data; he is rather viewed as a privileged being who has only to will that things be so, - so that the atheist does not have the least hesitation or scruple in pronouncing what we may call a verdict of non-existence.
Now it is here that the characteristic features of opinion appear in all their nakedness, in particular the externality of opinion relative to the very thing to which it refers. The more a state of affairs concerns me, the less I can say in the strict sense of the term that I have an opinion about it. Hence the justice of the remark which is wholly negative but still helps advance our inquiry, that commitment and opinion are mutually exclusive. This entails the metaphysical conclusion that I have an opinion about the universe only to the extent that I actually disengage myself from it (where I withdraw from the venture without evident loss). The pessimism of a modern disciple of Voltaire or of an Anatole France, for example, lies precisely in this: he is tied to a non-participation - to be sure we must note that this is not true of all pessimisms, and is not true of the pessimism of Schopenhauer, for example, to the extent that it is lived.
Atheism, however can be based not so much in an experience or the lack of an experience as on a claim, or more precisely, on a willing. A number of variable relations between this will and this experience or non-experience can be established.
“God,” writes Maritain, “is completely rejected in principle, as the result of an absolute metaphysical dogmatism . . . in the name of the social community, the collective or collectivised man. . . . The social communist ideal shows up as the conclusion of an initial atheism which has been postulated in principle.” I believe this to be quite true. But wouldn’t it be well to note that a kind of identity of attitude is realized here - paradoxically - between the collectivised man and the anarchist as Stirner, for example, has conceived him? It may be said by the way that we are touching here at the root of a paradox in which anarchism and communism tend to become identified in the minds of many people today. Here and there we encounter the same affirmation that man can only realize his full stature in a world devoid of God; and this, too, is why the idea or pseudo-idea of a communist humanism today tends to attract the attention of many minds whose principal talent, moreover does not appear to be the gift of reflection. As I have indicated, it is clear that this humanism is based not on an experience but on a claim. The hyperdoxical characteristic which we tried to exhibit earlier, fully reveals itself here. The more it grows, however, the more it becomes aware of itself - the more we tend to pass from the sphere of opinion into the sphere of faith.
However, someone may inquire whether it would not be appropriate to intercalate between opinion and faith an intermediate link, namely, conviction,
Here again we have to make a careful examination of certain realities that ordinary language - which is so loose - tends to conceal. “I have paraded my own convictions right and left,” a vaudeville character once said; “and they have remained unshakeable.” In this case there is no doubt that opinion and conviction coincide. On the other hand consider the case of a man who has arrived at a conviction on a specific question after patient effort and persistent inquiry: Scheurer-Kestner or Zola arriving at the conviction that Dreyfus was innocent, Conviction here refers to a limit, an end, a bar that has been drawn. My investigations can reveal nothing more, This means:: the cause is known to me; it is useless to talk about it further. Thus conviction in principle refers to the past; if it does refer to the future, it is an anticipated future, hence a future treated as though it were already past; there is in this respect a fundamental and also extremely subtle difference between conviction and prophetic certitude. Can we apply this observation to political or religious conviction? I believe we can. The person who professes his republican convictions thereby affirms that he has attained something which for him has a definitive character. The curious thing about this which is worth notice, however, is that the affirmation referring to the invariability of an inner disposition inevitably tends to become converted into a judgment asserting the immutability of its object. If I have republican convictions, I shall not be satisfied to say: “I shall always be convinced that a republic is the most rational political form”; I will go further and affirm: “a republic will always fulfill the desires of the most rational minds.” This is actually an irrational and unjustified inference, the psychological mechanism of which, however, instantly leaps to the eye.
Here I wish to strongly emphasize the word “definitive,” which I have just used. It is a word which embodies a claim to arrest time. Whatever you may say whatever happens, my conviction is unshakeable. It is worth the trouble to reflect a moment on the extravagant nature of this pretension, for it is one and eminently so. The individual does not confine himself to saying in effect: “Starting now, I am going to close my eyes and stop up my ears”: this would be a decision, not a pretension. No; what is affirmed is that “Whatever happens or whatever may be said cannot alter what I think.” Now we have one of two alternatives:
either I want to affirm by this that I have already anticipated in detail and refuted all the objections my questioners or the events themselves might confront me with;
or I affirm that these objections, whatever they may be - and this is tantamount to saying that I have not anticipated them, have not examined them in detail - cannot shake my conviction.
Let us consider the first alternative; it involves an absurdity. How can I be sure that I have anticipated all objections? The cases in which all the possibilities are enumerable are infinitely rare; one scarcely finds them except in pure logic or mathematics; and when I refer particularly to events which are by nature unpredictable, such an enumeration seems strictly inconceivable.
We must therefore fall back on the second alternative. Whatever objections there may be - I do not claim to predict them all in detail - I am determined not to take them into account. We fall from the level of pretense to that of decision, it is not certain, however, that we can remain there. I indicated that I am determined not to take them into account; but can I actually do this? Isn’t there a part of myself which is in danger of being influenced in certain ways which surrenders to a certain pressure? A part of myself which is relatively refractory to the power of control or domination that my will claims to exercise over the totality of myself? At the moment when I profess my unshakeable conviction, a concord, a harmony happens to be realized between the different parts of myself; will this harmony continue? It is impossible for me to affirm that it will in good faith; I cannot be responsible for what my state of feeling will be tomorrow. What then? If I were fully aware of these possibilities, these perils, I would say:
either: my conviction is unshakeable - except for the change in those parts of myself for which I cannot truly say I am responsible because they are in an immediate contact with the event; which is tantamount to saying that my conviction is not unshakeable, that I cannot sincerely state that it is so;
or: my conviction is unshakeable, whatever the changes that might occur in those areas of my inner realm which are not completely submissive; I decide once and for all that if inconsistencies should occur, they will have no repercussions on my conviction itself. However, the justification or the validity of this attitude is extremely doubtful. To be sure, if only my subsequent acts were involved, I could say: “Whatever happens, I will act as if . . . . But the zone of conviction is intermediary between that of feeling and that of action: and it is quite clear that between it and the zone of feeling there neither is nor can be any precise boundary. I must guard against the fact that at the moment I affirm my conviction, basing it on the harmony now realized within me, I cannot really envisage a different feeling, or better, dissonance, which I will experience tomorrow; I only have an abstract idea of it which I can juggle. Nothing more.
These reflections lead to the inference that the apposition of the terms definitive or unshakeable with the utterance of a conviction always implies a claim at the basis of which we can discern either as delusion or the consent to an inner life. All I really have the right to say is: “given the constellation of my present inner dispositions and the set of events of which I am now cognizant, I am inclined to think that. . . .” Moreover, I should guard against affirming the immutability of this constellation of factors on which my conviction is based, one which therefore seems to me to be essentially capable of being modified.
Doubtless this relativism will seem singularly cold to many readers, particularly prudent and timorous, and therefore incapable of giving that tonus, Γ©lan, or dynamic value to life in which we set so much store. What has happened all this time to belief? it will be asked. Isn’t it, too, infected by relativism? I do not think that it is, but the greatest care must be taken in showing this.
For the sake of clarifying remarks, I can say that the temporal orientation of belief is, in a way, the inverse of that of conviction. The latter refers to an arrest, to a bar that has been drawn; it implies a kind of inner closure. With belief, just the inverse is true. I am convinced that the bergsonian opposition between the open and the closed has a significantly novel application here.
However, we must guard against the pitfalls of language. The word believe is often used with the most fluctuating meanings; it sometimes means quite simply: “I assume that,” or even, “it seems to me that.” I do not believe we will succeed in extricating its essential characteristics unless we resolutely put to one side what is expressed by believing that (although there are some rare cases where this expression can be preserved). I shall concentrate first of all on what is implied in the act of belief in or about something or someone.
I think that the notion of credit can guide us in this context. To give, or better yet, open a credit account to someone. . . . This to my mind is the most essential and constitutive aspect of belief. We have to uncover its meaning. We must not be misled by the fact that to agree to extend credit is to place at the disposal of someone else a certain sum, a certain quantity of something, with the expectation that it will be returned to us together with an additional sum, a certain profit. We must unburden the meaning of extending credit of this material weight. I am in no way separable from that which I place at the disposal of this X (whose nature we must explore later). Actually, the credit that I extend is, in a way, myself. I lend myself to X. We should note at once that this is an essentially mysterious act.
To be sure, conviction, too, refers to something which is external to me; but it implies no commitment on my part towards this X. My conviction refers to X; I indicate my position with respect to X; I do not bind myself to X. I acknowledge that this is a very subtle difference, but it is a very important one to my mind. Believing means, to begin with, following a certain course, but only to the extent that following in no way means undergoing, but rather giving oneself, rallying to. The image evoked by rallying is possibly as instructive as that of credit; it connotes even more adequately the kind of inner gathering together presupposed by belief. It is interesting to note that this gathering together is the more effective to the extent that the belief is stronger. It is here that the analyses of Bergson are most clearly applicable. The strongest or most vital belief is one which brings all the powers of our being most completely into play - which does not mean that we can measure it exactly in terms of the consequences it implies on the plane of action. The human situation is infinitely more complex, and here as elsewhere, pragmatism proves to be inadequate.
Let us now consider this X to which we extend credit, to which we rally. What are its characteristics? I am prompted to say that it always is either a personal or a supra-personal reality; but the idea of a supra-personal reality raises difficulties which I can only touch upon. Whatever is on the hither side of the person always participates in thingness. But how can I put my trust in a thing - which is inert by definition, i.e., incapable of responding? This is only possible if I personalize this thing, if I make a fetish of it, a talisman, i.e., the incarnation of powers which are in reality those of the person himself. To believe in someone, is to put one’s trust in him, i.e.: “I am sure you will not let me down, that you will instead fulfill my expectations, that you will realize them.” I expressly use the second person here. One can only trust a “thou,” a reality capable of fulfilling the function of a “thou,” of being invoked, of becoming something I can fall back on. And it seems to me that this is of the utmost importance. It is clear, however, that this assurance is not a conviction in the sense I have described above; it goes beyond what is given, what I can experience, for it is an extrapolation, a leap, a bet, which like all bets, can be lost. The stakes involved are difficult to define - for the reason that it is I who am the credit which I extend to the other. I am convinced that in this context all our habitual categories of thought are inadequate. In a concrete philosophy we must almost invariably confront the drama concealed by the problem. As long as we think in terms of a problem we will see nothing, understand nothing; in terms of the drama or of mystery, however, the case may be somewhat different: as is so often true, it is negative experience, the experience of disappointment or defeat which is here the most revealing. I have placed my trust in a certain individual; he betrays me; if I had not established a completely inward relationship with him, or more precisely, with what I took to be him, this disappointment could not have touched me in the strict sense of the term; the fact is, however, that I am affected by it. This could result in a collapse for me, in a real uprooting of my being. What then has happened? That I have identified myself with this X and that I became partly alienated from myself because of him. (We must not forget the extending of credit). The result is that his failure is in a way my own. I find it impossible in this connection to adopt the detached attitude of the person who regrets what has happened but whom it “does not concern” in the final analysis. My disappointment is in a way a partial destruction of myself.
How was it possible to be disappointed, however? because my reliance on X had a conditional character. I counted on him to fulfill a certain task, for example: this task, as it happens, he did not fulfill; I ascribed a certain determinate quality to him; the event seems to demonstrate to me that he did not possess it. In sum, I had formed an idea of him which has now been contradicted and, as it were, nullified. In the light of my previous remarks, however, isn’t it plain that this vulnerability of my belief is linked to the residue of opinion still left in it? Here there are two boundary-cases which we must consider.
However strange it may seem to our minds, it is possible for there to be an unconditional love of creature for creature - a gift which will not be revoked. Whatever may occur, whatever disappointment experience inflicts on our hypotheses, our cherished hopes, this love will remain constant, this credit intact. Perhaps it is on data of this sort that the philosopher should first base his meditations when he tries to reflect on the absolute; for the most part these data are hardly ever taken into account. Examples like these, however, involve an anomaly which somehow seems to be suspended in a reality frequently unperceived by those very souls in which it blossoms. . . .
The other boundary-case is this: love is faith itself, an invincible assurance based on Being itself. It is here and here alone that we reach not only an unconditioned fact but a rational unconditional as well; namely that of the absolute Thou, that which is expressed in the Fiat voluntas tua of the Lord’s Prayer.
I shall not inquire here into the obscure, subterranean relation linking pure Faith in its ontological fullness with the unconditional love of creature for creature mentioned above. I deeply believe, however, that this link exists; and that this love is only conceivable, only possible, for a being who is capable of such faith, but a being in whom it has not yet been aroused; such a love is perhaps like a prenatal palpitation of faith.
There is, however, a further point on which I should like to make some concluding remarks; what are we to think of the secularized expression of faith of so many of our contemporaries? Faith in justice, faith in science, faith in progress, etc.?
Here we enter the realm of the supra-personal; yet in all cases such as these we are in fact clearly concerned with an order which can only be established by persons, and which, while above them in certain respects, nevertheless depends on their good faith.
Consider more specifically what “faith in science” means. I confess to some difficulty in determining what this can be.
The word “science” seems at the very outset to be stamped with a formidable ambiguity. Does the word designate a certain body of truths? If this is the case, it is really meaningless to refer to a faith in science. It is an abuse of language to apply the word “faith” to the mind’s adherence to a demonstrated truth. The fact is that those who have faith in science have faith in the influence exercised by those who have mastered a science. It is conceded that minds which are completely penetrated by scientific truth cannot but illuminate those other minds in which they in turn instill these truths. Hence if we do not want the sort of dictatorship of scientists as Renan, for example, conceived it, it seems clear that our hope must rest on the idea of an educational science, i.e., one which is endowed with the marvellous power of purifying those whom it illuminates.
I am very much afraid, however, that no worthwhile empirical or rational justification can be offered for this view. If a scientist can exercise a personal influence - this, moreover, is a pleonasm: what act is not personal? - this is not because of the truths that he disseminates, but because of the power of disinterestedness which animates him, or in other words, because he himself leads an exemplary life. It is an arbitrary distortion of meaning to imagine that the truths discovered by a patient and persevering inquiry somehow preserve a trace of these virtues, that the latter remain embodied in them; nothing of the sort occurs. Any truth, whatever it may be, considered apart from the fervor of the person who discovers it, is something ethically neutral, ethically inert. And this is more so to the extent that it is presented to us as more radically independent of those values it is the task of the mind to recognize and acknowledge.
Thus if we concentrate on the analysis of the meaning of this “faith in science” which our rationalists at the Sorbonne and elsewhere profess - and this is an extremely important task - we shall discover within it the most disparate elements.
As the basis of it we can discover a trace, an indistinct survival, as it were, of what another era apprehended as the attributes of Being and their mutual implications: for it is a plane on which the transcendentals are interconnected, where the True is inseparable from both the Good and the Beautiful. This plane, however, can by no means be identified with that of positive science; it is rather like an Atlantis of the mind - a submerged Atlantis.
If we want to describe the psychological mechanics which make this “faith in science” not only possible but effective, however, we have to turn to opinion and to opinion alone. In general, opinion, as we have noted, is defined as an appearing to be which tends to become converted into a claiming through an absence of reflection. Indeed I firmly believe that such a shift occurs in the present case. “Faith in science” is only explicable in terms of the phenomenon of prestige, and of an extrapolated prestige, if I may say so. It is appropriate to introduce here some reflections or observations borrowed from the concrete history of ideas. I do not believe that we can separate this scientific prestige which is envisaged by the imagination - not conceived - as liberative, from the corresponding representation of religion as a principle of spiritual slavery - as obscurantism. I do not believe I am mistaken in saying that the more weakened anticlericalism becomes the less we will be led to view science itself as a power of promethean emancipation.
I shall conclude my observations at this point; for it is not my purpose to continue with an examination of pure Faith. Again, as at the beginning of our discussion, I suggest that we view the foregoing as an indispensable introduction to the act of reflection, permitting us to discern at the core of our own beliefs what part is the truly incorruptible gold of Faith, and what part we must view, whatever the cost, as an unusable mass of slag, the dead weight opinion throws into the infinitely delicate scale of our spiritual acts.

What is faith?

Faith as Ultimate Concern


Paul Tillich (1886-1965) was born in Starzeddel in eastern Germany. He studied philosophy and theology and was ordained in the English Lutheran church. He served as an army chaplain during the first world war and then as a professor of theology and philosophy in various German universities. Later on he immigrated to the United States and taught systematic theology and philosophy of religion at Union Theological Seminary. He also taught at Harvard University and the University of Chicago Divinity School. Some of his works include The Religious Situation, Systematic Theology, and The Courage to Be.
The following selection, “What Faith Is,” is an excerpt from another of his works, The Dynamics of Faith, which is considered the best popular account of his philosophy of religion.
Tillich defines faith as “the state of being grasped by an ultimate concern, a concern which qualifies all other concerns as preliminary and which itself contains the answer to the question of the meaning of our life.” This ultimate concern refers to some definite value or set of values which serves for the believer as the focal point of his existence and to which all his other values and interests are somehow related and subordinated. It gives meaning and unity to the whole of his life, providing a way of organizing his experience and activity.
Faith as ultimate concern demands total surrender and the willingness to recognize this concern as an absolute authority. Tillich found in the commandment - “You shall love the Lord your God with all your heart, and with all your soul, and with all your might” (Deut. 6:5) - the clearest expression of this character of genuine faith, the complete surrender to the subject of ultimate concern. Faith therefore is an act of the total personality involving “every element in the centered self.”
This subjective act of faith, however, is not the only side of faith. Tillich distinguished between the “fides qua creditur” [the faith through which one believes] and the “fides quae creditur” [the faith which is believed.] Faith always involves a reference to a reality, the ultimate itself, which is expressed in religious symbols.

These two sides of faith, for Tillich, constitute a unity. “There is no faith without a content toward which it is directed… and there is no way of having the content of faith except in the act of faith.”



----------------------------------------------------------------------



WHAT FAITH IS

1. Faith as Ultimate Concern - Faith is the state of being ultimately concerned: the dynamics of faith are the dynamics of man’s the life of a social group extremely urgent, and each of them as well as the vital concerns can claim ultimacy for a human life or. If it claims ultimacy it demands the total surrender of him who accepts this claim, and it promises total fulfillment even if all other claims have to be subjected to it or rejected in its name. If a national group makes the life and growth of the nation its ultimate concern, it demands that all other concerns, economic well-being, health and life, family, aesthetic and cognitive truth, justice and humanity, be sacrificed. The extreme nationalisms of our century are laboratories for the study of what ultimate concern means in all ultimate concern. Man, like every living being, is concerned about many things, above all about those which condition his very existence, such as food and shelter. But man, in contrast to other living beings, has spiritual concerns—cognitive, aesthetic, social, political. Some of them are urgent, often aspects of human existence, including the smallest concern of one’s daily life. Everything is centered in the only god, the nation - a god who certainly proves to be a demon, but who shows clearly the unconditional character of an ultimate concern.
But it is not only the unconditional demand made by that which is one’s ultimate concern, it is also the promise of ultimate fulfillment which is accepted in the act of faith. The content of this promise is not necessarily defined. It can be expressed in indefinite symbols or in concrete symbols which cannot be taken literally, like the “greatness” of one’s nation in which one participates even if one has died for it, or the conquest of mankind by the “saving race,” etc. In each of these cases it is “ultimate fulfillment” that is promised, and it is exclusion from such fulfillment which is threatened if the unconditional demand is not obeyed.
An example - and more than an example - is the faith manifest in the religion of the Old Testament. It also has the character of ultimate concern in demand, threat and promise. The content of this concern is not the nation—although Jewish nationalism has sometimes tried to distort it into that—but the content is the God of justice, who, because he represents justice for everybody and every nation, is called the universal God, the God of the universe. He is the ultimate concern of every pious Jew, and therefore in his name the great commandment is given: “You shall love the Lord your God with all your heart, and with all your soul, and with all your might” (Deut. 6:5). This is what ultimate concern means and from these words the term “ultimate concern” is derived. They state unambiguously the character of genuine faith, the demand of total surrender to the subject of ultimate concern. The Old Testament is full of commands which make the nature of this surrender concrete, and it is full of promises and threats in relation to it. Here also are the promises of symbolic indefiniteness, although they center around fulfillment of the national and individual life, and the threat is the exclusion from such fulfillment through national extinction and individual catastrophe. Faith, for the men of the Old Testament, is the state of being ultimately and unconditionally concerned about Jahweh and about what he represents in demand, threat and promise.
Another example - almost a counter-example, yet nevertheless equally revealing - is the ultimate concern with “success” and with social standing and economic power. It is the god of many people in the highly competitive Western culture and it does what every ultimate concern must do: it demands unconditional surrender to its laws even if the price is the sacrifice of genuine human relations, personal conviction, and creative eros. Its threat is social and economic defeat, and its promise - indefinite as all such promises - the fulfillment of one’s being. It is the breakdown of this kind of faith which characterizes and makes religiously important most contemporary literature. Not false calculations but a misplaced faith is revealed in novels like Point of No Return. When fulfilled, the promise of this faith proves to be empty.
Faith is the state of being ultimately concerned. The content matters infinitely for the life of the believer, but it does not matter for the formal definition of faith. And this is the first step we have to make in order to understand the dynamics of faith.

2. Faith as a Centered Act - Faith as ultimate concern is an act of the total personality. It happens in the center of the personal life and includes all its elements. Faith is the most centered act of the human mind. It is not a movement of a special section of a special function of man’s total being. They all are united in the act of faith. But faith is not the sum total of their impacts. It transcends every special impact as well as the totality of them and it has itself a decisive impact on each of them.
Since faith is an act of the personality as a whole, it participates in the dynamics of personal life. These dynamics have been described in many ways, especially in the recent developments of analytic psychology. Thinking in polarities, their tensions and their possible conflicts, is a common characteristic of most of them. This makes the psychology of personality highly dynamic and requires a dynamic theory of faith as the most personal of all personal acts. The first and decisive polarity in analytic psychology is that between the so-called unconscious and the conscious. Faith as an act of the total personality is not imaginable without the participation of the unconscious elements in the personality structure. They are always present and decide largely about the content of faith. But, on the other hand, faith is a conscious act and the unconscious elements participate in the creation of faith only if they are taken into the personal center which transcends each of them. If this does not happen, if unconscious forces determine the mental status without a centered act, faith does not occur, and compulsions take its place. For faith is a matter of freedom. Freedom is nothing more than the possibility of centered personal acts. The frequent discussion in which faith and freedom are contrasted could be helped by the insight that faith is a free, namely, centered act of the personality. In this respect freedom and faith are identical.
Also important for the understanding of faith is the polarity between what Freud and his school call ego and superego. The concept of the superego is quite ambiguous. On the one hand, it is the basis of all cultural life because it restricts the uninhibited actualization of the always-driving libido; on the other hand, it cuts off man’s vital forces, and produces disgust about the whole system of cultural restrictions, and brings about a neurotic state of mind. From this point of view, the symbols of faith are considered to be expressions of the superego or, more concretely, to be an expression of the father image which gives content to the superego. Responsible for this inadequate theory of the superego is Freud’s naturalistic negation of norms and principles. If the superego is not established through valid principles, it becomes a suppressive tyrant. But real faith, even if it uses the father image for its expression, transforms this image into a principle of truth and justice to be defended even against the “father.” Faith and culture can be affirmed only if the superego represents the norms and principles of reality.
This leads to the question of how faith as a personal, centered act is related to the rational structure of man’s personality which is manifest in his meaningful language, in his ability to know the true and to do the good, in his sense of beauty and justice. All this, and not only his possibility to analyze, to calculate and to argue, makes him a rational being. But in spite of this larger concept of reason we must deny that man’s essential nature is identical with the rational character of his mind. Man is able to decide for or against reason, he is able to create beyond reason or to destroy below reason. This power is the power of his self, the center of self-relatedness in which all elements of his being are united. Faith is not an act of any of his rational functions, as it is not an act of the unconscious, but it is an act in which both the rational and the nonrational elements of his being are transcended.
Faith as the embracing and centered act of the personality is “ecstatic.” It transcends both the drives of the nonrational unconscious and the structures of the rational conscious. It transcends them, but it does not destroy them. The ecstatic character of faith does not exclude its rational character although it is not identical with it, and it includes nonrational strivings without being identical with them. In the ecstasy of faith there is an awareness of truth and of ethical value; there are also past loves and hates, conflicts and reunions, individual and collective influences. “Ecstasy” means “standing outside of oneself” - without ceasing to be oneself - with all the elements which are united in the personal center.
A further polarity in these elements, relevant for the understanding of faith, is the tension between the cognitive function of man’s personal life, on the one hand, and emotion and will, on the other hand. In a later discussion I will try to show that many distortions of the meaning of faith are rooted in the attempt to subsume faith to the one or the other of these functions. At this point it must be stated as sharply and insistently as possible that in every act of faith there is cognitive affirmation, not as the result of an independent process of inquiry but as an inseparable element in a total act of acceptance and surrender. This also excludes the idea that faith is the result of an independent act of "will to believe.” There is certainly affirmation by the will of what concerns one ultimately, but faith is not a creation of the will. In the ecstasy of faith the will to accept and to surrender is an element, but not the cause. And this is true also of feeling. Faith is not an emotional outburst: this is not the meaning of ecstasy. Certainly, emotion is in it, as in every act of man’s spiritual life. But emotion does not produce faith. Faith has a cognitive content and is an act of the will. It is the unity of every element in the centered self. Of course, the unity of all elements in the act of faith does not prevent one or the other element from dominating in a special form of faith but it does not create the act of faith.
This also answers the question of a possible psychology of faith. Everything that happens in man’s personal being can become an object of psychology. And it is rather important for both the philosopher of religion and the practical minister to know how the act of faith is embedded in the totality of psychological processes. But in contrast to this justified and desirable form of a psychology of faith there is another one which tries to derive faith from something that is not faith but is most frequently fear. The presupposition of this method is that fear or something else from which faith is derived is more original and basic than faith. But this presupposition cannot be proved. On the contrary, one can prove that in the scientific method which leads to such consequences faith is already effective. Faith precedes all attempts to derive it from something else, because these attempts are themselves based on faith.
3. The Source of Faith – We have described the act of faith and its relation to the dynamics of personality. Faith is a total and centered act of the personal self, the act of unconditional, infinite and ultimate concern. The question now arises: what is the source of this all-embracing and all-transcending concern? The word “concern” points to two sides of a relationship, the relation between the one who is concerned and his concern. In both respects we have to imagine man’s situation in itself and in his world. The reality of man’s ultimate concern reveals something about his being, namely, that he is able to transcend the flux of relative and transitory experiences of his ordinary life. Man’s experiences, feelings, thoughts are conditioned and finite. They not only come and go, but their content is of finite and conditional concern – unless they are elevated to unconditional validity. But this presupposes the element of infinity in man. Man is able to understand in an immediate personal and central act the meaning of the ultimate, the unconditional, the absolute, the infinite. This alone makes faith a human potentiality. Human potentialities are powers that drive toward actualization. Man is driven toward faith by his awareness of the infinite to which he belongs, but which he does not own like a possession. This is in abstract terms what concretely appears as the “restlessness of the heart” within the flux of life.
The unconditional concern which is faith is the concern about the unconditional. The infinite passion, as faith has been described, in the passion for the infinite. Or, to use our first term, the ultimate concern about what is experienced as ultimate. In this way we have turned from the subjective meaning of faith as a centered act of the personality to its objective meaning, to what is meant in the act of faith. It would not help at this point of our analysis to call that which is meant in the act of faith “God” or “a god.” For at this step we ask: What in the idea of God constitutes divinity? The answer is: It is the element of the unconditional and of ultimacy. This carries the quality of divinity. If this is seen, one can understand why almost everything “in heaven and on earth” has received ultimacy in the history of human religion. But we can understand that a critical principle was and is at work in man’s religious consciousness, namely, that which is really ultimate over against what claims to be ultimate but is only preliminary, transitory, finite.
The term “ultimate concern” unites the subjective and objective side of the act of faith – the fides qua creditur (the Faith through which one believes) and the fides quae creditur (the faith which is believed). The first is the classical term for the centered act of the personality, the ultimate concern. The second is the classical term for that toward which this act is directed, the ultimate itself, expressed in symbols of the divine. This distinction is very important, but not ultimately so, for the one side cannot be with the other. There is no faith without the content toward which it is directed. There is always something meant in the act of faith. All speaking about divine matters which is not done in the state of ultimate concern is meaningless. Because that which is meant in the act of faith cannot be approached in any other way than through an act of faith.
In terms like ultimate, unconditional, infinite, absolute, the difference between subjectivity and objectivity is overcome. The ultimate of the act of faith and the ultimate that is meant in the act of faith are one and the same. This is symbolically expressed by the mystics when they say that their knowledge of God is the knowledge God has of himself and it is expressed by Paul when he says (1 Cor. 13) that he will know as he is known, namely, by God. God never can be object without being at the same time subject. Even a successful prayer is according to Paul ( Rom. 8), not possible without God as Spirit praying within us. The same experience expressed in abstract language is the disappearance of the ordinary subject-object scheme in the experience of the ultimate, the unconditional. In the act of faith that which is the source of this act is present beyond the cleavage of subject and object. It is –present as both and beyond both.
This character of faith gives an additional criterion for distinguishing true and false ultimacy. The finite which claims infinity without having it (as, e.g., a nation or success) is not able to transcend the subject-object scheme. It remains an object which the believer looks at as a subject. He can approach it with ordinary knowledge and subject it to ordinary handling. There are, of course, many degrees in the endless realm of false ultimacies. The nation is nearer to true ultimacy than in success. Nationalistic ecstacy can produce a state in which the subject is almost swallowed by the object. But after the period the subject emerges again, disappointed radically and totally, and by looking at the nation in a skeptical and calculating way does injustice even to its justified claims. The more idolatrous a faith the less it is able to overcome the cleavage between subject and object. For that is the difference between true and idolatrous faith. In true faith, the ultimate concern is a concern about the truly ultimate; while in idolatrous faith preliminary, finite realities are elevated to the rank of ultimacy. The inescapable consequence of idolatrous faith is “existential disappointment,” a disappointment which penetrates into the very existence of man! This is the dynamics of idolatrous faith, and as such, the centered act of a personality; that the centering point is something which is more or less on to the periphery; and that, therefor, the act of faith leads to a loss of the center and to a disruption of the personality. The ecstatic character of even an idolatrous faith can hide this consequence only for a certain time. But finally it breaks into the open.

SYMBOLS OF FAITH
1. The Meaning of Symbol – Man’s ultimate concern must be expressed symbolically, because symbolic language alone is able to express the ultimate. This statement demands explanation in several respects. In spite of the manifold research about the meaning and function of symbols which is going on in contemporary philosophy, every writer who uses the term “symbol” must explain his understanding of it.
Symbols have one characteristic in common with signs; they point beyond themselves to something else. The red sign at the street corner points to the order to stop the movements of cars at certain intervals. A red light and the stopping of cars have essentially no relation to each other, but conventionally they are united as long as the conventions lasts. The same is true of letters and numbers and partly even words. They point beyond themselves to sounds and meanings. They are given this special function by convention within a nation or by international conventions, as the mathematical signs. Sometimes such signs are called symbols; but this is unfortunate because it makes the distinction between signs and symbols more difficult. Decisive is the fact that signs do not participate in the reality of that to which they point, while symbols do. Therefore, signs can be replaced for reasons of expediency or convention, while symbols cannot.
This leads to the second characteristic of the symbol: It participates in that to which it points: the flag participates in the power and dignity of the nation for which it stands. Therefore, it cannot be replaced except after an historic catastrophe that changes the reality of the nation which it symbolizes. An attack on the flag is felt as an attack on the majesty of the group in which it is acknowledged. Such an attack is considered blasphemy.
The third characteristic of a symbol is that it opens up levels of reality which otherwise are closed for us. All arts create symbols for a level of reality which cannot be reached in any other way. A picture and a poem reveal elements of reality which cannot be approached scientifically. In the creative work of art we encounter reality in a dimension which is closed for us without such works. The symbol’s fourth characteristic not only opens up dimension and elements of reality which otherwise would remain unapproachable but also unlocks dimensions and elements of our soul which correspond to the dimensions and elements of reality. A great play gives us not only a new vision of the human scene, but it opens up hidden depths of our own being. Thus we are able to receive what the play reveals to us in reality. There are within us dimensions of which we cannot become aware except through symbols, as melodies and rhythms in music.
Symbols cannot be produced intentionally- this is the fifth characteristic. They grow out of the individual or collective unconscious and cannot function without being accepted by the unconscious dimension of our being. Symbols which have an especially social function, as political and religious symbols, are created or at least accepted by the collective unconscious in the group in which they appear.
The sixth and last characteristics of the symbol is a consequence of the fact that symbols cannot be invented. Like living beings, they grow and they die. They grow when the situation is ripe for them, and they die when the situation changes. The symbol of the “king” grew in a special period of history, and it died in most parts of the world in our period. Symbols do not grow because people are longing for them, and they do not die because they no longer produce response in the group where they originally found expression.
These are the main characteristics of every symbol. Genuine symbols are created in several spheres of man’s cultural creativity. We have mentioned already the political and the artistic realm. We could add history and, above all, religion, whose symbols will be our particular concern.

2. Religious Symbols – We have discussed the meaning of symbols generally because, as we said, man’s ultimate concern must be expressed symbolically! One may ask: Why can it not be expressed directly and properly? If money, success or the nation is someone’s ultimate concern, can this not be said in a direct way without symbolic language? Is it not only in those cases in which the content of the ultimate concern is called “God” that we are in the realm of symbols? The answer is that everything which is a matter of unconditional concern is made into a god. If the nation is someone’s ultimate concern, the name of the nation becomes a sacred name and the nation receives divine qualities which far surpass the reality of the being and functioning of the nation. The nation the stands for and symbolizes the true ultimate, but in an idolatrous way. Success as ultimate concern is not the national desire of actualizing potentialities, but is readiness to sacrifice all other values of life for the sake of a position of power and social predominance. The anxiety about not being a success is an idolatrous form of the anxiety about divine condemnation. Success is grace; lack of success, ultimate judgement. In this way concepts designating ordinary realities become idolatrous symbols of ultimate concern.
The reason for this transformation of concepts into symbols is the character of ultimacy and the nature of faith. That which is the true ultimate transcends the realm of finite reality infinitely. Therefore, no finite reality can express it directly and properly. Religiously speaking, God transcends his own name. This is why the use of his name easily becomes an abuse or a blasphemy. Whatever we say about that which concerns us ultimately, whether or not we call it God, has a symbolic meaning. It points beyond itself while participating in that to which it points. In no other way can faith express itself adequately. The language of faith is the language of symbols. If faith were what we have shown that is not, such an assertion could not be made. But faith, understood as the state of being ultimately concerned, has no language other than symbols. When saying this I always expect the question: Only a symbol? He who asks this question shows that he has not understood the difference between signs and symbols nor the power of symbolic language, which surpasses in quality and strength the power of any nonsymbolic language. One should never say “only a symbol,” but one should say “not less than a symbol.” With this in mind we can now describe the different kinds of symbols of faith.
The fundamental symbol of our ultimate concern is God. It is always present in any act of faith, even if the act of faith includes the denial of God. Where there is ultimate concern, God can be denied only in the name of God. One God can deny its own character as ultimate. Therefore, it affirms what is meant by the word “God”. Atheism, consequently, can only mean the attempt to remove any ultimate concern-to remain unconcerned about the meaning of one’s existence. Indifference toward the ultimate question is the only imaginable form of atheism. Whether it is possible is a problem which must remain unsolved at this point. In any case, he who denies God as a matter of ultimate concern affirms God, because he affirms ultimacy in his concern. God is the fundamental symbol for what concerns us ultimately. Again it would be completely wrong to ask: So God is nothing but a symbol? Because the next question has to be: A symbol for what? And then the answer would be: For God! God is symbol for God. This means that in the notion of God we must distinguish two elements: the element of ultimacy, which is a matter of immediate experience and not symbolic in itself, and the element of concreteness, which is taken from our ordinary experience and symbolically applied to God. The man whose ultimate concern is a sacred tree has both the ultimacy of concern and the concreteness of the tree which symbolizes his relation to the ultimate. The man who adores Apollo is ultimately concerned, but not in an abstract way. His ultimate concern is symbolized in the divine figure of Apollo. The man who glorifies Yahweh, the God of the Old Testament, has both an ultimate concern and a concrete image of what concerns him ultimately. This is the meaning of the seemingly cryptic statement that God is the symbol of God. In this qualified sense God is the fundamental and universal content of faith.
It is obvious that such an understanding of the meaning of God makes the discussions about the existence or nonexistence of God meaning less. It is meaningless to question the ultimacy of an ultimate concern. This element is the idea of God is in itself certain. The symbolic expression of this element varies endlessly through the whole history of mankind . Here again it would be meaningless to ask whether one or another of the figures in which an ultimate concern is symbolized does “exist.” If “existence” refers to something which can be found within the whole of reality, no divine being exists. The question is not this, but: which of the innumerable symbols of faith is most adequate to the meaning of faith? In other words, which symbol of ultimacy expresses the ultimate without idolatrous elements? This is the problem, and not the so-called “existence of God” –which is in itself an impossible combination of words. God as the ultimate in man’s ultimate concern is more certain than any other certainty, even that of oneself. God as symbolized in a divine figure is a matter of daring faith, of courage and risk.
God is the basic symbol of faith, but not the only one. All the qualities we attribute to him, power, love, justice, are taken from finite experiences and applied symbolically to that which is beyond finitude and infinity. If faith calls God “almighty,” it uses the human experience of power in order to symbolize the content of its infinite concern, but it does not describe a highest being who can do as he pleases. So it is with all the other qualities and with all actions, past, present and future, which men attribute to God. They are symbols taken from our daily experience, and not information about what God did once upon a time or will do sometime in the future. Faith is not the belief in such stories, but it is the acceptance of symbols that express our ultimate concern in terms of divine actions.
Another group of symbols of faith are manifestations of the divine in things and events, in persons and communities, in words and documents. This whole realm of sacred objects is a treasure of symbols. Holy things are not holy in themselves, but they point beyond themselves to the source of all holiness, that which is of ultimate concern.